Philosophy Guides

How to Come up with a Paper Topic (Thesis) 


Author: Rooke Christy 

Originally Posted: 3/3/2023


“And for the final essay of the class, you will choose your own paper topic.” 


Ok, but how? You can find some interesting suggestions here at the philosophers’ cocoon. However, I wanted a systematic way to generate thesis ideas, so I came up with one (inspired by the book The Pyramid Principle by Barbara Minto).


Importantly, this is a method for coming up with thesis ideas. I am not instructing you on how to build a successful argument (not today, at least). Additionally, I cannot show you how to come up with good ideas. (Personally, I think the fear of Bad Ideas inhibits people’s creativity; let yourself brainstorm low quality ideas! Give your mind permission to make connections).


Instead of reading aimlessly to try to find a topic, with this method you can come up with potential thesis ideas and then do directed research to (see if it’s possible to) support your favorite thesis idea. 


Summary of methods:


Method 1: From Scratch

i. Something could go wrong (how do things tend to go wrong in your area of interest?)

ii. Here’s three alternatives

iii. Here’s someone with a different point of view (“someone” could be you!)

i. Something could go wrong →

ii. Here’s 3 alternatives →

a. Which alternative should we accept (if any)? 

b. Why shouldn’t we accept one of these alternatives?

iii. Here’s someone with a different pov →

a. Who is right? 

b. Are all wrong? 

c. Should we combine the views somehow?



Method 2: Ideas from abstracts or readings

i. What are some alternative answers to the question? Is there reason to prefer a different answer?

ii. What are some related questions that we could answer? Does answering any of these related questions help us answer the original question?

iii. What assumptions do you have to make to ask this question? Can any of these assumptions be questioned?

iv. Why is this question important?

i. Against the author

a.  Is there something wrong with the author’s answer? 

ii. Charitable Reading: 

b. Is part of the author’s argument unclear? How can you make the author’s argument clearer? 



For a walkthrough of the steps, read on!

I(a). Coming up with Ideas From Scratch


In discussing how to write an introduction to a business memo (/email/document/etc), Barbara Minto says that we need to state a recognized, stable situation within which a complication develops, which raises the question to which the document gives the answer (pp. 37). How is this relevant to philosophy (or academic writing more generally)? Philosophy essays do this exact thing! (Though they usually don’t explicitly state the question).


 The key to generating ideas is to hone in on the implicit questions papers are answering. Coming up with ideas is hard because we’re trying to come up with answers without first identifying any questions that need answering. So, let’s identify some questions!




In more detail….

1. Identify a situation/status quo/statement of fact. 


What is a recognized stable Situation? Some kind of status quo. Most birds fly. X person is the current US President. Most philosophers are compatibilists about free will. Many things could be a “situation”. Let’s take the existence of a material world. 



2. Identify a complication for the situation. 


What could be a Complication? Minto offers seven ways a Complication could arise, each with a corresponding Question to answer in your written work. Here are three Complications: Something could go wrong; here’s three alternatives; here’s someone with a different point of view


3. Identify questions that arise from the Complication

Complication 1- Something could go wrong: Someone could kidnap us and connect us to a computer simulated world, much like in the Matrix movies. 


Question: How can we prevent it?

This question doesn’t quite work for philosophy papers (though answering it could make an interesting movie or sci fi short story). Let’s try instead, “What worries does this potential situation bring up, and how can we address these concerns?”


The worries you come up with will likely depend on your area of interest. For example:


Epistemology

What are the implications for knowledge? Are there skeptical implications? Does this (at least logical, if not actual) possibility have consequences for our ability to know things in everyday life? Can we learn something about the nature of knowledge from this example? (Full disclosure, my area is epistemology.)


Metaphysics

Would objects in a virtual world still be real objects? Do I have hands in a simulated world? (David Chalmers has some interesting papers on the metaphysics of virtual reality, by the way) Is there anything internally inconsistent about viewing reality this way? Is there a reason to think our reality is actually a simulation?


Ethics

What does a simulated world mean for my obligations to others? If reality is simulated, does this mean I can do whatever I want? 


4. What are some potential answers?


Example of Answer/thesis


Complication 2- Here are three alternatives: We have the possibility of computer simulation already. Perhaps we’re dreaming. Perhaps we’re a figment of some creature/deity’s imagination.


Question: Which alternative should we take? Or, which alternative should we accept (if any)? Why shouldn’t we accept one of these alternatives?


Example of Answer/thesis:


Complication 3- Someone with a different pov: George Berkely and his idealism is a well-known possibility. Perhaps you yourself are another possibility, if you have a unique point of view to offer.


Question: Who is right? Are all wrong? Should we combine the views somehow?


Example of Answers/theses (+ potential choices for argumentation)



I(b). Example:


Alright, let’s look at an example using an abstract from a paper:


https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqaa084 The Paradox of Pain by Adam Bradley


Abstract


Bodily pain strikes many philosophers as deeply paradoxical. The issue is that pains seem to bear both physical characteristics, such as a location in the body, and mental characteristics, such being mind-dependent. In this paper I clarify and address this alleged paradox of pain. I begin by showing how a further assumption, Objectivism, the thesis that what one feels in one’s body when one is in pain is something mind-independent, is necessary for the generation of the paradox. Consequently, the paradox can be avoided if one rejects this idea. However, doing so raises its own difficulties, for it is not obvious how anything can possess all of the features we typically associate with bodily pain. To address this puzzle and finally put the paradox of pain to rest, I develop the Embodied View, a novel metaphysical account on which pains are constitutively mind-dependent features of parts of a subject’s body.


First, let’s note how Bradley follows the method outlined above. 


Bradley (1) Identifies a Situation. AKA, the status quo. Philosophers see pain as paradoxical, because pain has both physical (mind independent) and mental (mind dependent) characteristics.


(2) Complication (for the status quo): His use of words like “seem” and “alleged” imply the complication: Actually this is not a paradox at all. 


(3) This complication gives rise to the Question Bradley will answer in his paper: How could this not be a paradox? Or, how could we resolve this seeming paradox?


(4) Bradley’s paper provides the Answer: We can resolve the paradox by rejecting objectivism, a necessary assumption for generating the paradox


II. Coming Up With Ideas From Readings


So, the above works if you have a situation in mind already. But what if you don’t, and you need to generate ideas for undergraduate philosophy classes or papers more generally? We reverse-engineer the above process.


1. Pick a philosophy reading.

2.  Identify statements the author makes. 

3. What question(s) are the statements answering? Identify the questions. 

4. Either provide an alternative answer to this question, or identify a further question that you can answer in your own paper. Some further questions might include:

i. What are some alternative answers to the question? Is there reason to prefer a different answer?

ii. What are some related questions that we could answer? Does answering any of these related questions help us answer the original question?

iii. What assumptions do you have to make to ask this question? Can any of these assumptions be questioned?

iv. Why is this question important?


You also have these popular options:

- Against the author

i. Is there something wrong with the author’s answer? 

-Charitable Reading: 

i. Is part of the author’s argument unclear? How can you make the author’s argument clearer? 

5. Create an argument for your answer to one of the questions in step 4. (As noted earlier, constructing the actual argument to support your thesis goes beyond the scope of my article)



Let’s apply these steps to Bradley’s abstract. We’ve satisfied step 1.


Step 2: Let’s extract some statements.

Pain seems paradoxical;  pain seems to bear both physical and mental (mind dependent) characteristics; the paradox can be avoided if we reject objectivism; difficulties arise from rejecting objectivism; the metaphysical account Bradley develops (the embodied view) addresses the difficulties that arise from rejecting objectivism.


Step 3: What questions are these statements answering?


i. the paradox can be avoided if we reject objectivism; 

ii. difficulties arise from rejecting objectivism: 

iii. The embodied view addresses the difficulties that arise from rejecting objectivism: 


Step 4: Identify a further question you can answer in your own paper. 

i. How can we avoid the paradox of pain?

ii. Can we discard objectivism?


IIb. Sample ideas-turned-thesis


Some Sample thesis statements responding to Bradley (a-c are separate theses you could choose between):


Bradley argues that rejecting Objectivism to resolve the paradox of pain leads to complications. He resolves these complications by developing the Embodied View. In this paper I will argue that…


The next step would be to do research to see if the thesis you chose can be adequately argued/supported. Thus, we can partake in directed reading for the sake of research, instead of reading widely in an aimless manner hoping to figure out what we might want to research.


Hope this helps someone else. Feel free to send an email with suggestions and questions to kchris37@jhu.edu.







Student Guide for Coming Up with Reading Questions 

The following guide was made for students in the class Intro to Bioethics. I refer to a specific assignment in this guide, but the strategies should work for coming up with questions from readings more generally, too.


Author: Rooke Christy 

Originally Posted: 9/7/2024


Here are some strategies for coming up with a question from a reading.

 

List of Strategies (with detailed explanation below the list)

 

Strategy I: Identify alternatives that the author has not (satisfactorily) considered and question whether the author's argument works, given that the author has not addressed one of the alternatives.

 

Strategy II. Find two authors with conflicting views and turn it into a question

 

Strategy III Identify unwanted consequences of the author's views that the author does not satisfactorily address

 

Strategy IV. Identify assumptions the author is relying on and question these assumptions

 

Strategy V. Try to summarize the main points in the paper and see if you find yourself struggling to do so clearly. Sometimes we think we understand something but when we go to summarize it, we might realize that there are parts that we understand less than we realized. A question may come to us through this exercise. 

 

 

Strategy I.

Identify alternatives that the author has not (satisfactorily) considered and question whether the author's argument works, given that the author has not addressed one of the alternatives.

 

(1) First, identify claims the author makes that the author actually agrees with.

 

Here are some quotes from the last paragraph of Alan Goldman's "The Refutation of Medical Paternalism":

 

(a) "Autonomy or self-determination is independently valuable, as argued before, first of all because we value it in itself."

 

(b) "What has value does so because it is valued by a rational and autonomous person."

 

(2) From here, ask yourself, "What question(s) could this statement be an answer to?" (These questions will likely be too broad to work for the weekly question)

 

Why is autonomy or self-determination independently valuable?
Is autonomy or self-determination independently valuable?

How could we recognize that something is independently valuable if it is?

 

 What does it mean for something to have value? Why does something with value have value? What is it that makes something valuable?

 

 

(3) What are some other ways that we might answer one of these questions?

 

((a) question)  Is autonomy or self-determination independently valuable?

 

a1. Nothing is independently valuable.

 

a2. value is culturally-determined. A culture could instead value conformity and living according to how  others tell you to live (Eg, parents pick child's spouse and career path; government tells some people that they will join the military and this is seen as an acceptable normal thing in the culture)

 

((b) question) "What is it that makes something valuable?"

 

b1: If something is valuable, that's because of something about the thing itself. Even if no one values it, it is still valuable. Eg, you might think humans or nature inherently have value, even if they are not valued by anyone.

 

b2: Whether something has value depends on the particular cultural context. There are no universal standards for what is valuable.

 

b3: Nothing is valuable in any meaningful way. People value things but that is a fact about the "value-er", not the thing that is being valued.

 

(4) Has the author (convincingly) ruled out these alternatives? Are any of these alternatives something you could imagine someone actually believing?

See if you can construct a question about whether the author has satisfactorily justified their claim, or whether the author has considered all the possiblities, etc.

 

 

Question: has Goldman done enough to justify his claim that "(a) "Autonomy or self-determination is independently valuable, as argued before, first of all because we value it in itself"? Explanation:  it's not clear to me that he has done enough to justify this claim.  It seems possible that value is determined by cultural context. There could very well be a culture that does not value autonomy or self-determination, but perhaps thinks something else is more valuable (like obedience to authority figures).

 

Question: has Goldman done enough to rule out alternatives to his claim (b) "What has value does so because it is valued by a rational and autonomous person"?  Explanation: It seems possible that if something is valuable, it is valuable because of something about it, and not because a rational and autonomous person values it. It doesn't seem right that a human infant has no value if no rational or autonomous person values it.

 

(5) Now try to tie it more clearly to the reading. Try to relate it to something specific in the reading.

(The syllabus says: Questions and their explanations should concern some specific aspect of the assigned reading).

 

Question: has Goldman done enough to justify his claim that "(a) "Autonomy or self-determination is independently valuable, as argued before, first of all because we value it in itself"?

Explanation:  it's not clear to me that he has done enough to justify this claim.  It seems possible that value is determined by cultural context. There could very well be a culture that does not value autonomy or self-determination, but perhaps thinks something else is more valuable (like obedience to authority figures).

(Added Part) A patient in a culture like this may prefer a physician just tell them their expert opinion of what the patient should do, instead of giving the patient options. But Goldman does not give us any reason to believe his claim (a) over the claim that autonomy or self-determination is only valuable if the cultural context says it is. Without addressing these possibilities, Goldman's success at refuting paternalism could be limited by the culture of the physician and patient involved.

 

Question: has Goldman done enough to rule out alternatives to his claim (b) "What has value does so because it is valued by a rational and autonomous person"?

Explanation: It seems possible that if something is valuable, it is valuable because of something about it, and not because a rational and autonomous person values it. It doesn't seem right that a human infant has no value if no rational or autonomous person values it.

(Added Part) This certainly does not seem like a view we want to endorse in healthcare. If no rational or autonomous person values a patient, the patient surely still has value. In summary, I do not think Goldman has ruled out convincing alternatives to his claim, and I think accepting his claim would imply that some patients may not have value, which seems like a reason to reject his claim.

 

 

(6) You could also look through the reading to see if there are any other relevant things to add to your explanation.

   

 

Other Methods

 

Strategy II. 

Find two authors with conflicting views and turn it into a question

 

1. When doing the readings, try to keep in mind whether any two authors have clearly opposing views. There are likely many ways this could be turned into a question, but one such way is:

Is there a reason one author gives to support their view that the other author fails to address? This can be turned into a question.

 

In the readings for 9/2, we received commentary where some people endorsed keeping the unconscious patient "Monica" unconscious and (paternalistically) making decisions for her. At least one other author of a different Commentary argued we should wake Monica.

 

Question: Does Bernice S. Elger underestimate the effects of illness on a patient when arguing we should wake Monica?

Explanation: Elger discusses a situation where a woman, Monica, is... (explain situation). Elger argues that we should wake Monica, giving reasons such as allowing her to arrange her affairs if she wishes, or say goodbye to loved ones.

However, Terrence E. Ackerman argues that illness can bring a loss of control, and if a physician does not consider the way illness changes a patient, then simply telling the patient the truth or giving the patient options may not be enough to support patient autonomy. Elger suggests some ways to manage the physically uncomfortable parts of waking up for Monica, but if Monica wakes up in this state, the psychological impacts of her current ill state may also have an impact on her ability to be truly autonomous.

 

 

Strategy III. 

Identify unwanted consequences of the author's views that the author does not satisfactorily address

 

1.  Identify statements the author makes that the author agrees with. If we take these statements as true what else would also be true? Can we find an example where this statement seems to lead to a result that is unideal/bad/unwanted?

 

"Question: Does the author provide enough support for (statement), given the unaddressed undesirable consequences? Explanation: (explain the unaddressed undesirable consequences and make sure the question engages with specific parts of the reading)

 

Question: Can we really accept the statement "What has value does so because it is valued by a rational and autonomous person"?  given consequences of this statement that the author has not addressed?

Explanation: This statement seems to imply that if no autonomous or rational person values something or someone then that thing or person is not valuable. This seems like a bad conclusion in a healthcare setting because... (insert explanation). While Goldman gives some argument for thinking that self-determination is independently valuable, I cannot find any real argument for the quoted statement, and do not see how we can accept it if he has not addressed this negative consequence of taking the statement to be true.

 

Strategy IV. 

Identify assumptions the author is relying on and question these assumptions

 

1. Again, pick out some statements that the author makes. Does this statement appear to involve any assumptions?

 

2. If you're unsure...  Come up with questions that these statements could be an answer to. Does this question appear to make any assumptions?

 

3. Can any of these assumptions be questioned? Are the assumptions justified?

 

"[w]hen patients are initially asked to participate in the decision-making process, some exhibit considerable confusion and anxiety. Thus, for many persons, the institutional role of patient requires the physician to assume the responsibilities of making decisions." (SLA pp 73)

 

 

If a patient exhibits considerable confusion and anxiety when initially asked to participate in a decision making process, a physician is required to assume the responsiblity of making decisions for their patient.

 

 

Example Question:

 

Question: Why does the author think that a physician is required to assume the responsibility of making decisions for their patient if their patient acts really confused or anxious when asked to participate in a decision-making process?

Explantation: The author does not address any of the alternative possibilities available to the patient, such as (....). This makes it difficult to see why the physician would be required to make the patient's decisions. Additionally, what counts as "considerable" confusion and anxiety? And is the patient confused about the fact they are being involved in the decision process, or confused because they do not understand what the doctor is trying to explain to them? Either way, it remains unclear why the doctor is required to make decisions for the patient instead of first trying to reduce the patient's confusion."